Amphithéâtre Marguerite de Navarre, Site Marcelin Berthelot
Open to all
-

The third lecture reiterated the starting hypotheses and the precautions to be taken: properties, without which we would have no cognitive access to things, are defined essentially by the dispositions and causal powers they exert. On the one hand, there are essential properties and accidental properties - the challenge being: how do we distinguish between them? And on the other, there are also laws. If we want to avoid "pandispositionalism", we have to start from the premise that some properties are not "essentially" dispositional. Finally, there is more than one step from concept to thing: we must not confuse "predicates" and "properties", and we must distinguish between "power" and "properties" by virtue of which things have the powers they have. From here, we have presented the characteristics of narrow essentialism or aliquidditism. The starting point is Avicennian and Scotian. The principle of neutrality and irreducibility of common nature is adopted. Certain metaphysical realities or formalities can be reduced neither to physical supposits nor to conventional names, since their real unity, if indeed discovered by the intellect, is not produced by it. Aliquidditism is not quidditism: there is no primitivehaecceitas (" primitive thisness "). This involves a re-elaboration of the Scotian model: essence is not a static "quiddity", or a substance, or a pure natural species, or a pure bundle of habits, but rather a fundamentally dispositional "aliquid" something. The real source of intelligibility of a thing (" operari sequitur esse ") is not its behavior (too static a conception of essence), but a set ofhabits or general dispositions affecting the way it would tend to behave in certain kinds of circumstances: essence is not intrinsic properties, but conditional and mutual relational or dispositional properties,clusters of causal powers.

References

[12] Schaffer J., "Quiddistic knowledge", Philosophical Studies, 123, 2005, 1-32.