Amphithéâtre Marguerite de Navarre, Site Marcelin Berthelot
Open to all
-

The second lecture began by looking at the strength of our essentialist intuitions, and the bad press that essentialism suffers from at the same time. Indeed, if we all have the impression that things could have been otherwise than they are, and that not all the properties of things are essential to them, we find it difficult to distinguish between the essential and the purely accidental (Mackie [1]): no doubt it seems more essential to this person in front of me that he belongs to the human species, and more accidental that he has blond hair. I also find it hard to imagine that my substance could turn into a poached egg, and I naturally believe that I have more in common with a human being than with a donkey or a cauliflower. But after all, what do I know? And, more importantly, how do I account for it? Such is the challenge posed to essentialism. For while it's true that our intuitions lead us to find that, in reality, certain articulations are more natural than others, we've also learned to be wary of our impressions and imagination, which we know can, without a moment's hesitation, send us waltzing off on the side of illusions and prejudices. What's more, when it's not purely and simply suspected of "speciesism" or the most conservative naturalism, essentialism finds itself associated with the bygone era when metaphysics was the queen of the sciences, and when some imagined that by giving the "essential" definition of a stone, by exhibiting both its formal and final cause (the nature of a thing being its end), we would know, from the outset, why the said stone fell: it's because it wants to return to its natural place, which is the Earth (Aristotle). This rejection by scientists and philosophers alike, heirs to the linguistic turn and logical empiricism (see Quine), is not unfounded. Who would still dream of essences, if by that we mean mysterious, anhistorical entities fixed once and for all? Hasn't essentialism been refuted by scientific discoveries such as Darwinism? Isn't all reality subject to the laws of evolution? As John Locke once said: if we want to talk about essences, that's fine: but only on condition that we see in them "nominal" definitions, not "real" ones, and above all that we don't seek in them any knowledge of things [2]. But, as we've seen, Leibniz's ambition was quite different. A certain revival of essentialism in contemporary metaphysics, which in the 1970s went hand in hand with a renewed interest in metaphysics (see last year's lecture), particularly in the forms it took in the analyses of Kripke [3] and Putnam [4], less linked to the "substantialist" conception that Quine was aiming for [5], would rather go in his direction. Since then, discussions on essentialism have been in full swing: attacks by some (Fine [6]) on the modal conception of essence (Kripke and Putnam), but also the development of new forms: scientific essentialism (Ellis [7]), four-dimensional, neo-Aristotelian ontology (Lowe [8]).

References

[1] Mackie P., How Things Might Have Been: Individuals, Kinds, and Essential Properties, Oxford, Oxford UP, 2009. See also l.a. Paul, "the context of essence", Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82 (1), 2004, 170-184; republished in Jackson F. and Priest G.(eds.), Lewisian Themes, Oxford UP; "in defense of essentialism", Philosophical Perspectives, 20 (Metaphysics), 2006, 333-372.

[2] See last year's lecture; see also Ayers M., "Locke versus Aristotle on natural kinds", The Journal of Philosophy, 78(5), 1981, 247-272 and Leary N., "How essentialists misunderstand Locke", History of Philosophy Quarterly, 26, 2009, 273-92.

[3] Kripke S., Naming and Necessity, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1980; French translation by F. Récanati and P. Jacob, La logique des noms propres, Paris, Minuit, 1984.

[4] Putnam H., "The meaning of 'meaning'", in Gunderson K. (ed.), Language,Mindand Knowledge: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, VII, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1975, reprinted in Putnam H., Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, vol. II, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 215-71; "Is water necessarilyH2O?", in Conant J. (ed.), Realism with a Human Face, Cambridge (Mass.), Harvard University Press, 1990, 54-79, French translation by C. Tiercelin, Le Réalisme à visage humain, Paris, Gallimard, 1991.

[5] Quine W. V., "Natural kinds", in Rescher N. (ed.), Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel, Dordrecht, D. Reidel, 1969, 5-23.

[6] Fine K. "Essence and modality", Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1994, 1-16.

[7] Ellis B., Scientific Essentialism, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2001.

[8] Lowe E. J., The Four-Category Ontology: a Metaphysical Foundation for Natural Science, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006. See also Oderberg D. S., Real Essentialism, Abingdon and New York, Routledge, 2007.

[9] Ladyman J., Ross D., Spurrett D. & Collier J., Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2007.

[10] Tiercelin C., Le Ciment des choses. Petit traité de métaphysique scientifique réaliste, Itaque, 2011, 247-359.